Sortition

Not to be confused with Démarche.

In governance, sortition (also known as allotment or demarchy) selects officers as a random sample from a larger pool of candidates.[1]

In ancient Athenian democracy, sortition was the traditional and primary method for appointing political officials and its use was regarded as a principal characteristic of democracy.[2]

Sortition is commonly used to select prospective jurors in common law-based legal systems and is sometimes used today in forming citizen groups with political advisory power (citizens' juries or citizens' assemblies).[3]

History

The following is a brief history of sortition's implementation, as it applies specifically to governance, and (when specified) the judiciary system.

Ancient Athens

Athenian democracy developed in the 6th century BC out of what was then called isonomia (equality of law and political rights). Sortition was then the principal way of achieving this fairness. It was utilized to pick most[4] of the magistrates for their governing committees, and for their juries (typically of 501 men). Aristotle relates equality and democracy:

Democracy arose from the idea that those who are equal in any respect are equal absolutely. All are alike free, therefore they claim that all are free absolutely... The next is when the democrats, on the grounds that they are all equal, claim equal participation in everything.[5]
It is accepted as democratic when public offices are allocated by lot; and as oligarchic when they are filled by election.[6]

In Athens, "democracy" (literally meaning rule by the people) was in opposition to those supporting a system of oligarchy (rule by a few). Athenian democracy was characterised by being run by the "many" (the ordinary people) who were allotted to the committees which ran government. Thucydides has Pericles make this point in his Funeral Oration: "It is administered by the many instead of the few; that is why it is called a democracy."[7]

A kleroterion in the Ancient Agora Museum (Athens)

The Athenians believed sortition to be more democratic than elections[4] and used complex procedures with purpose-built allotment machines (kleroteria) to avoid the corrupt practices used by oligarchs to buy their way into office. According to the author Mogens Herman Hansen the citizen's court was superior to the assembly because the allotted members swore an oath which ordinary citizens in the assembly did not and therefore the court could annul the decisions of the assembly. Both Aristotle[4] and Herodotus (one of the earliest writers on democracy) emphasize selection by lot as a test of democracy, "The rule of the people has the fairest name of all, equality (isonomia), and does none of the things that a monarch does. The lot determines offices, power is held accountable, and deliberation is conducted in public."[8]

Past scholarship maintained that sortition had roots in the use of chance to divine the will of the gods, but this view is no longer common among scholars.[9] In Ancient Greek mythology, Zeus, Poseidon, and Hades used sortition to determine who ruled over which domain. Zeus got the sky, Poseidon the sea, and Hades the underworld.

In Athens, to be eligible to be chosen by lot, citizens self-selected themselves into the available pool, then lotteries in the kleroteria machines. The magistracies assigned by lot generally had terms of service of 1 year. A citizen could not hold magistracy more than once in his lifetime, but could hold other magistracies. All male citizens over 30 years of age, who were not disenfranchised by atimia, were eligible. Those selected through lot underwent examination called dokimasia in order to avoid incompetent officials. Rarely were selected citizens discarded.[10] Magistrates, once in place, were subjected to constant monitoring by the Assembly. Magistrates appointed by lot had to render account of their time in office upon their leave, called euthynai. However, any citizen could request the suspension of a magistrate with due reason.[11]

Northern Italy and Venice – 12th to 18th century

The brevia was used in the city states of Northern Italy during the 12th and 13th centuries and in Venice until the late 18th century.[12] Men, who were chosen randomly, swore an oath that they were not acting under bribes, and then they elected members of the council. Voter and candidate eligibility probably included property owners, councilors, guild members, and perhaps, at times, artisans. The Doge of Venice was determined through a complex process of nomination, voting and sortition.

Lot was used in the Venetian system only in order to select members of the committees that served to nominate candidates for the Great Council. A combination of election and lot was used in this multi-stage process. Lot was not used alone to select magistrates, unlike in Florence and Athens. The use of lot to select nominators made it more difficult for political sects to exert power, and discouraged campaigning.[10] By reducing intrigue and power moves within the Great Council, lot maintained cohesiveness among the Venetian nobility, contributing to the stability of this republic. Top magistracies generally still remained in the control of elite families.[13]

Florence – 14th and 15th century

The scrutiny was employed in Florence for over a century starting in 1328.[12] Nominations and voting together created a pool of candidates from different sectors of the city. These men then had their names deposited into a sack, and a lottery draw determined who would get magistracy positions. The scrutiny was gradually opened up to minor guilds, reaching the greatest level of renaissance citizen participation in 1378–82.

In Florence, lot was used to select magistrates and members of the Signoria during republican periods. Florence utilized a combination of lot and scrutiny by the people, set forth by the ordinances of 1328.[10] In 1494, Florence founded a Great Council in the model of Venice. The nominatori were thereafter chosen by lot from among the members of the Great Council, indicating a decline in aristocratic power.[14]

Switzerland

Because financial gain could be achieved through the position of mayor, some parts of Switzerland used random selection during the years between 1640 and 1837 in order to prevent corruption.[15]

India

Local government in parts of Tamil Nadu such as the village of Uttiramerur traditionally used a system known as kuda-olai where the names of candidates for the village committee were written on palm leaves and put into a pot and pulled out by a child.[16]

Today

In the political realm, sortition occurs most commonly in order to form policy juries, such as deliberative opinion polls, citizens' juries, Planungszelle (planning cells), consensus conferences, and citizens' assemblies. As an example, Vancouver council has initiated a citizens' assembly that will meet in 2014–15 in order to assist in city planning.[17]

Sortition is commonly used in selecting juries in Anglo-Saxon legal systems and in small groups (e.g., picking a school class monitor by drawing straws). In public decision-making, individuals are often determined by allotment if other forms of selection such as election fail to achieve a result. Examples include certain hung elections and certain votes in the UK Parliament. Some contemporary thinkers have advocated a greater use of selection by lot in today's political systems, for example reform of the British House of Lords and proposals at the time of the adoption of the current Constitution of Iraq.

Sortition is also used in military conscription, in awarding US green cards, and in placing students into public schools, into one California nursing college, and into schools of medicine in the Netherlands.[18]

Modern examples

Political proposals for sortition

Sortition as part of reworking the state

Sortition to replace elected legislative bodies

Sortition to decide the franchise

Sortition to supplement or replace some of the legislators

Sortition to replace an appointed upper house

Advantages

Effective representation of the interests of the people

A modern advocate of sortition, political scientist John Burnheim, argues for systems of sortition as follows:

Let the convention for deciding what is our common will be that we will accept the decision of a group of people who are well informed about the question, well-motivated to find as good a solution as possible and representative of our range of interests simply because they are statistically representative of us as a group. If this group is then responsible for carrying out what it decides, the problem of control of the execution process largely vanishes.[38]

This advantage does not equally apply to the use of juries.

Cognitive Diversity

Cognitive diversity is an amalgamation of different ways of seeing the world and interpreting events within it,[39] where a diversity of perspectives and heuristics guide individuals to create different solutions to the same problems.[40] Cognitive diversity is not the same as gender, ethnicity, value-set or age diversity, although they are often positively correlated. According to numerous scholars such as Page and Landemore, cognitive diversity is more important to creating successful ideas than the average ability level of a group. This "Diversity Trumps Ability Theorem[41]" is essential to why sortition is a viable democratic option.[40] Simply put, random selection of persons of average intelligence performs better than a collection of the best individual problem solvers.[40]

Fairness and equality

Sortition is inherently egalitarian in that it ensures all citizens have an equal chance of entering office irrespective of any bias in society:[42]

Compared to a voting system – even one that is open to all citizens – a citizen-wide lottery scheme for public office lowers the threshold to office. This is because ordinary citizens do not have to compete against more powerful or influential adversaries in order to take office, and because the selection procedure does not favour those who have pre-existing advantages or connections – as invariably happens with election by preference.[43]

Random selection has the ability to overcome the various demographic biases in race, religion, sex, etc. apparent in most legislative assemblies. Greater perceived fairness can be added by using stratified sampling. For example, the Citizens' Assembly on Electoral Reform in British Columbia sampled one woman and one man from each electoral district and also ensured representation for First Nations members. Bias may still exist if particular groups are purposefully excluded from the lottery such as happened in Ancient Athens where women, slaves, younger men and foreigners were not eligible.

Democratic

Greek writers who mention democracy (including Aristotle,[4] Plato and Herodotus) emphasise the role of selection by lot or state outright that being allotted is more democratic than elections. For example, Plato says:

Democracy arises after the poor are victorious over their adversaries, some of whom they kill and others of whom they exile, then they share out equally with the rest of the population political offices and burdens; and in this regime public offices are usually allocated by lot.[44]

The idea that democracy is associated with sortition remained common in the 18th century. Charles de Secondat, baron de Montesquieu writes in The Spirit of the Laws, "The suffrage by lot is natural to democracy, as that by choice is to aristocracy."[45]

Anti-corruption

Sortition may be less corruptible than voting. Author James Wycliffe Headlam explains that the Athenian Council (500 administrators randomly selected), would commit occasional mistakes such as levying taxes that were too high. Additionally, from time to time, some in the Council would improperly make small quantities of money from their civic positions. However, "systematic oppression and organized fraud were impossible".[46] These Greeks recognized that sortition broke up factions, diluted power, and gave positions to such a large number of disparate people that they would all keep an eye on each other making collusion fairly rare. Furthermore, power did not necessarily go to those who wanted it and had schemed for it. The Athenians used an intricate machine, a kleroterion, to allot officers. Headlam also explains that "the Athenians felt no distrust of the lot, but regarded it as the most natural and the simplest way of appointment".[47]

Like Athenian democrats, critics of electoral politics in the 21st-century argue that the process of election by vote is subject to manipulation by money and other powerful forces and because legislative elections give power to a few powerful groups they are believed to be less democratic system than selection by lot from amongst the population.

Empowering ordinary people

An inherent problem with electoral politics is the over-representative of the politically active groups in society who tend to be those who join political parties. For example, in 2000 less than 2% [48] of the UK population belonged to a political party whilst in 2005 there were at best only 3 independent MPs (see List of UK minor party and independent MPs elected) so that 99.5% of all UK MPs belonged to a political party. As a result, political members of the UK population were represented by one MP per 1800 of those belonging to a party whilst those who did not belong to a party had one MP per 19 million individuals who did not belong to a party.

Alleviates the problems of voter fatigue

Supporters also argue that sortition alleviates the problems of voter fatigue and rational ignorance, which is seen as a problem in both representative democracy and direct democracy.

Loyalty is to conscience not to political party

Elected representatives typically rely on political parties in order to gain and retain office. This means they often feel a primary loyalty to the party and will vote contrary to conscience to support a party position. Representatives appointed by sortition do not owe anything to anyone for their position.

Disadvantages

Pure sortition does not discriminate

The most common argument against pure sortition (that is, with no prior selection of an eligible group) is that it does not discriminate among those selected and takes no account of particular skills or experience that might be needed to effectively discharge the particular offices to be filled. Were such a position to require a specific skill set, sortition could not necessarily guarantee the selection of a person whose skills matched the job requirement unless the group from which the allotment is drawn were itself composed entirely of sufficiently specialized persons. The Athenians, for example, did not fill the roles of military commander (Strategos) by sortition for this reason. By contrast, systems of election or appointment ideally limit this problem by encouraging the matching of skilled individuals to jobs they are suited to. By submitting their qualifications to scrutiny beforehand, either by the electorate or other persons in positions of authority, those manifestly unqualified to hold a given position can be prevented from being elected or appointed to discharge it.

According to Xenophon (Memorabilia Book I, 2.9), this classical argument was offered by Socrates:

[Socrates] taught his companions to despise the established laws by insisting on the folly of appointing public officials by lot, when none would choose a pilot or builder or flautist by lot, nor any other craftsman for work in which mistakes are far less disastrous than mistakes in statecraft.[49]

The same argument is also made by Edmund Burke in his essay Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790):

There is no qualification for government but virtue and wisdom, actual or presumptive. [...] Everything ought to be open, but not indifferently, to every man. No rotation; no appointment by lot; no mode of election operating in the spirit of sortition or rotation can be generally good in a government conversant in extensive objects. Because they have no tendency, direct or indirect, to select the man with a view to the duty or to accommodate the one to the other.[50]

Chance misrepresentation

Because it introduces randomness in determining outcomes, there is always the statistical possibility that sortition may put into power an individual or group that do not represent the views of the population from which they were drawn. This argument is mentioned by Isocrates in his essay Areopagiticus (section 23):

[It was] considered that this way of appointing magistrates [i.e., elections] was also more democratic than the casting of lots, since under the plan of election by lot chance would decide the issue and the partizans of oligarchy would often get the offices; whereas under the plan of selecting the worthiest men, the people would have in their hands the power to choose those who were most attached to the existing constitution.[51]

This argument applies to juries, but less to larger groups where the probability of, for example, an oppressive majority, are statistically insignificant.

Voting confers legitimacy

Those who see voting as expressing the "consent of the governed", maintain that voting is able to confer legitimacy in the selection. According to this view, elected officials can act with greater authority than when randomly selected.[52] With no popular mandate to draw on, politicians lose a moral basis on which to base their authority. As such, politicians would be open to charges of illegitimacy, as they were selected purely by chance.

Individuals not chosen for enthusiasm

In an elected system, the representatives are to a degree self-selecting for their enthusiasm for the job. Under a system of pure, universal sortition the individuals are not chosen for their enthusiasm.[10] Many electoral systems assign to those chosen a role as representing their constituents; a complex job with a significant workload. Elected representative choose to accept any additional workload; voters can also choose those representatives most willing to accept the burden involved in being a representative. Individuals chosen at random from a comprehensive pool of citizens have no particular enthusiasm for their role and therefore may not make good advocates for a constituency.[32]

Lack of feedback or accountability

Unlike elections, where members of the elected body may stand for re-election, sortition does not offer a mechanism by which the population expresses satisfaction or dissatisfaction with individual members of the allotted body. Thus, under sortition there is no formal feedback, or accountability, mechanism for the performance of officials, other than the law.[10]

Methods

Before the random selection can be done, the pool of candidates must be defined. Systems vary as to whether they allot from eligible volunteers, from those screened by education, experience, or a passing grade on a test, or screened by election by those selected by a previous round of random selection, or from the membership or population at large. A multi-stage process in which random selection is alternated with screening for merit, called fetura, from the Latin for breeding, the same method used in genetic or [evolutionary algorithms], can overcome the risk of selecting those who lack ability or enthusiasm. But, by creating definitions that are not equal to the actual characteristics of the group many of the benefits, like getting realistic data that people continuously choose not to vote (due to lack of enthusiasm) or clear legislation that can be interpreted without special ability, will be compromised as happens with any researcher's data when the data that will be analysed is altered before conclusions are made.

USCAR Court select juries by sortition

The selection method may need to be carefully designed in order to preserve public confidence that it has not been rigged. The process may be conducted or supervised by a panel themselves selected at random, such as a grand jury being used to administer the random selection of the next grand jury.

One robust, general, public method of allotment in use since 1997 is documented in RFC 3797: Publicly Verifiable Nominations Committee Random Selection. Using it, multiple specific sources of random numbers (e.g. lotteries) are selected in advance, and an algorithm is defined for selecting the winners based on those random numbers. When the random numbers become available, anyone can calculate the winners.

David Chaum, a pioneer in computer science and cryptography, proposed Random-Sample Elections in 2012. Via recent advances in computer science, it is now possible to select a random sample of eligible voters in a verifiably valid manner and empower them to study and make a decision on a matter of public policy. This can be done in a highly transparent manner which allows anyone to verify the integrity of the election, while optionally preserving the anonymity of the voters. A related approach has been pioneered by James Fishkin, director of the Center for Deliberative Democracy at Stanford, to make legally binding decisions in Greece, China and other countries.[53][54]

See also

References

  1. Landemore, Hélène (January 15, 2010). "Deliberation, Representation, and the Epistemic Function of Parliamentary Assemblies: a Burkean Argument in Favor of Descriptive Representation" (PDF). International Conference on "Democracy as Idea and Practice," University of Oslo. Retrieved November 2, 2015.
  2. Headlam, James Wycliffe (1891). Election by Lot at Athens. p. 12.
  3. Fishkin, James (2009). When the People Speak: Deliberative Democracy & Public Consultation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199604432.
  4. 1 2 3 4 The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes, Mogens Herman Hansen, ISBN 1-85399-585-1
  5. Aristotle, Politics 1301a28-35
  6. Aristotle, Politics 4.1294be
  7. Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War. The Funeral Oration of Pericles.
  8. Herodotus The Histories 3.80.6
  9. Bernard Manin, The Principles of Representative Government
  10. 1 2 3 4 5 Manin, Bernard (1997). The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-45891-9.
  11. Hansen, M. H. (1981). Election by Lot at Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  12. 1 2 Dowlen, Oliver (2008). The Political Potential of Sortition: A study of the random selection of citizens for public office. Imprint Academic.
  13. Rousseau (1762). On the Social Contract. New York: St Martin's Press. p. 112.
  14. Brucker, Gene (1962). Florentine Politics and Society 1342-1378. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  15. Carson, Lyn; Martin, Brian (1999). Random Selection in Politics. Praeger. p. 33.
  16. Uttaramerur (a village near Kanchipuram in the
  17. "City of Vancouver Grandview-Woodland Community Plan". Retrieved 22 August 2014.
  18. Boyle, Conall (2010). Lotteries for Education. Exeter: Imprint Academic.
  19. Leonard, Kimberly (2016-02-23). "Christians Find Their Own Way to Replace Obamacare". US News & World Report. Retrieved 2016-03-22.
  20. Friedrich August von Hayek: Law, legislation and liberty, Volume 3, pp. 38–40.
  21. Burnheim, John (1985). Is Democracy Possible?. University of California Press.
  22. Allin Cottrell, Paul Cockshott, "Towards a new Socialism", 1991. pg 167
  23. León, L (1988). The World-Solution for World-Problems: The Problem, Its Cause, Its Solution. ISBN 90-900259-2-8.
  24. Brian Martin, "Demarchy: A Democratic Alternative to Electoral Politics", Kick It Over, No. 30, Fall 1992, pp. 11–13. Archived December 28, 2007, at the Wayback Machine.
  25. The World Solution for World Problems, Chapter: A Concept for Government, León
  26. Lottokratie Entwurf einer postdemokratischen Gesellschaft: Band 4 der Reihe: Geschichte der Zukunft by Christopher Frey, 16 June 2009, ISBN 978-3839105405
  27. "Instituting Meritocracy After the Collapse of Democracy in America - LewRockwell LewRockwell.com". LewRockwell.com. Retrieved 2016-05-12.
  28. Callenbach, Ernest; Phillips, Michael (1985). A Citizen Legislature. Berkeley/Bodega California: Banyan Tree Books/ Clear Glass.
  29. "Populiste n’est pas un gros mot", entretien avec Etienne Chouard Archived August 28, 2012, at the Wayback Machine.
  30. Sortition as a sustainable protection against oligarchy Conference by Etienne Chouard
  31. C. L. R. James, Every Cook Can Govern, 1956.
  32. 1 2 "Democracy Through Multi-Body Sortition" by Terrill G. Bouricius
  33. Comment on "Rundle: you call this democracy? It's time to start again", Crikey, Melbourne, August 19, 2010.
  34. Mitchell, Jack; Mitchell, David (22 September 2005). "Athens on the Hill: A plan for a Neo-Athenian Parliament in Canada". National Post. pp. A23.
  35. Sutherland, Keith (2008). A People's Parliament. Imprint Academic.
  36. Donovan, Michael (2012). Political Sortition for an Evolving World. Simon Fraser University. p. 83.
  37. Barnett, Anthony; Carty, Peter (2008). The Athenian Option: Radical Reform for the House of Lords (2nd ed.). Imprint Academic.
  38. Burnheim, John (2006). Is Democracy Possible?. University of California Press. pp. 124–5. ISBN 978-1920898427.
  39. Landemore, Helene (2012). "Deliberation, Cognitive Diversity, and Democratic Inclusiveness: An Epistemic Argument for the Random Selection of Representatives". Sythese.
  40. 1 2 3 Page (2007). How the power of diversity creates better groups, firms, schools, and societies. Princeton University Press.
  41. Dreifus, Claudia (January 8, 2008). "New York Times". In Professor's Model, Diversity= Productivity.
  42. https://books.google.com/books?id=V3nZCgAAQBAJ&pg=PP31&lpg=PP31&dq=Sortition+qi&source=bl&ots=3M89JlQfWz&sig=6-nX4ElAB-2OWFtBwvJDcOhulaU&hl=en&sa=X&ved=0ahUKEwjCxL_14LXLAhVX3mMKHXaRB0YQ6AEIODAE#v=onepage&q&f=false
  43. Oliver Dowlen, Sorting Out Sortition: A Perspective on the Random Selection of Political Officers Political Studies 2008
  44. Plato, Republic VIII, 557a
  45. Charles de Secondat, baron de Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws, Book 2, Chapter 2
  46. Headlam, James Wycliffe (1891). Election by Lot at Athens. p. 77.
  47. Headlam, James Wycliffe (1891). Election by Lot at Athens. p. 96.
  48. http://www.perfect.co.uk/2004/09/the-decline-of-the-political-party
  49. Xenophon. Memorabilia Book I, 2.9
  50. Edmund Burke (1790), Reflections on the Revolution in France
  51. Isocrates. Areopagiticus (section 23)
  52. "Advantages of Sortition". Sortitionist.com. Retrieved 2015-12-11.
  53. "How Selecting Voters Randomly Can Lead to Better Elections". Wired.com. 2012-05-16. Retrieved 2014-03-12.
  54. David Chaum (2012). "Random-Sample Elections: Far lower cost, better quality and more democratic" (PDF). Retrieved 2014-03-12.
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 12/4/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.