Responsive set extension

In utility theory, the responsive set (RS) extension is an extension of a preference-relation on individual items, to a partial preference-relation of item-bundles.

Example

Suppose there are four items: . A person tells us that he ranks the items according to the following total order:

(i.e, z is his best item, then y, then x, then z). Assuming the items are independent goods, we can deduce that:

- the person preferes his two best items to his two worse items;
- the person preferes his best and 3rd-best items to his 2nd- and 4th-best items.

But, we cannot deduce anything about the bundles ; we do not know which of them the person prefers.

The RS extension of the ranking is a partial order on the bundles of items, that includes all relations that can be deduced from the item-ranking and the independence assumption.

Definitions

Let be a set of objects and a total order on .

The RS extension of is a partial order on . It can be defined in several equivalent ways.[1]

Responsive Set (RS)

The original RS extension[2]:44–48 is constructed as follows. For every bundle , every item and every item , take the following relations:

The RS extension is the transitive closure of these relations.

Pairwise Dominance (PD)

The PD extension is based on a pairing of the items in one bundle with the items in the other bundle.

Formally, if-and-only-if there exists an Injective function from to such that, for each , .

Stochastic Dominance (SD)

The SD extension (named after stochastic dominance) is defined not only on discrete bundles but also on fractional bundles (bundles that contains fractions of items). Informally, a bundle Y is SD-preferred to a bundle X if, for each item z, the bundle Y contains at least as many objects, that are at least as good as z, as the bundle X.

Formally, iff, for every item :

where is the fraction of item in the bundle .

If the bundles are discrete, the definition has a simpler form. iff, for every item :

Additive Utility (AU)

The AU extension is based on the notion of an additive utility function.

Many different utility functions are compatible with a given ordering. For example, the order is compatible with the following utility functions:

Assuming the items are independent, the utility function on bundles is additive, so the utility of a bundle is the sum of the utilities of its items, for example:

The bundle has less utility than according to both utility functions. Moreover, for every utility function compatible with the above ranking:

.

In contrast, the utility of the bundle can be either less or more than the utility of .

This motivates the following definition:

iff, for every additive utility function compatible with :

Equivalence

Therefore, the four extensions and and and are all equivalent.

Responsiveness

A total order on bundles is called responsive[4]:287–288 if it is contains the responsive-set-extension of some total order on items.

Responsiveness is implied by additivity, but not vice versa:

See also

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 Aziz, Haris; Gaspers, Serge; MacKenzie, Simon; Walsh, Toby (2015). "Fair assignment of indivisible objects under ordinal preferences". Artificial Intelligence. 227: 71. arXiv:1312.6546Freely accessible. doi:10.1016/j.artint.2015.06.002.
  2. Barberà, S., Bossert, W., Pattanaik, P. K. (2004). "Ranking sets of objects.". Handbook of utility theory (PDF). Springer US.
  3. Katta, Akshay-Kumar; Sethuraman, Jay (2006). "A solution to the random assignment problem on the full preference domain". Journal of Economic Theory. 131: 231. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2005.05.001.
  4. Brandt, Felix; Conitzer, Vincent; Endriss, Ulle; Lang, Jérôme; Procaccia, Ariel D. (2016). Handbook of Computational Social Choice. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781107060432. (free online version)
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 11/21/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.