Proof that e is irrational

The number e was introduced by Jacob Bernoulli in 1683. More than half a century later, Euler, who had been a student of Jacob's younger brother Johann, proved that e is irrational, that is, that it can not be expressed as the quotient of two integers.

Euler's proof

Euler wrote the first proof of the fact that e is irrational in 1737 (but the text was only published seven years later).[1][2][3] He computed the representation of e as a simple continued fraction, which is

Since this continued fraction is infinite and every rational number has a terminating continued fraction, e is irrational. A short proof of the previous equality is known.[4] Since the simple continued fraction of e is not periodic, this also proves that e is not a root of second degree polynomial with rational coefficients; in particular, e2 is irrational.

Fourier's proof

The most well-known proof is Joseph Fourier's proof by contradiction,[5] which is based upon the equality

Initially e is assumed to be a rational number of the form ab. Note that b couldn't be equal to one as e is not an integer. It can be shown using the above equality that e is strictly between 2 and 3.

We then analyze a blown-up difference x of the series representing e and its strictly smaller bth partial sum, which approximates the limiting value e. By choosing the magnifying factor to be the factorial of b, the fraction ab and the bth partial sum are turned into integers, hence x must be a positive integer. However, the fast convergence of the series representation implies that the magnified approximation error x is still strictly smaller than 1. From this contradiction we deduce that e is irrational.

Suppose that e is a rational number. Then there exist positive integers a and b such that e = ab. Define the number

To see that if e is rational, then x is an integer, substitute e = ab into this definition to obtain

The first term is an integer, and every fraction in the sum is actually an integer because n  b for each term. Therefore, x is an integer.

We now prove that 0 < x < 1. First, to prove that x is strictly positive, we insert the above series representation of e into the definition of x and obtain

because all the terms are strictly positive.

We now prove that x < 1. For all terms with nb + 1 we have the upper estimate

This inequality is strict for every n  b + 2. Changing the index of summation to k = n  b and using the formula for the infinite geometric series, we obtain

Since there is no integer strictly between 0 and 1, we have reached a contradiction, and so e must be irrational. Q.E.D.

Alternate proofs

Another proof[6] can be obtained from the previous one by noting that

and this inequality is equivalent to the assertion that bx < 1. This is impossible, of course, since b and x are natural numbers.

Still another proof[7] can be obtained from the fact that

Generalizations

In 1840, Liouville published a proof of the fact that e2 is irrational[8] followed by a proof that e2 is not a root of a second degree polynomial with rational coefficients.[9] This last fact implies that e4 is irrational. His proofs are similar to Fourier's proof of the irrationality of e. In 1891, Hurwitz explained how it is possible to prove along the same line of ideas that e is not a root of a third degree polynomial with rational coefficients.[10] In particular, e3 is irrational.

More generally, eq is irrational for any non-zero rational q.[11]

See also

References

  1. Euler, Leonhard (1744). "De fractionibus continuis dissertatio" [A dissertation on continued fractions] (PDF). Commentarii academiae scientiarum Petropolitanae. 9: 98–137.
  2. Euler, Leonhard (1985). "An essay on continued fractions". Mathematical Systems Theory. 18: 295–398. doi:10.1007/bf01699475.
  3. Sandifer, C. Edward (2007). "Chapter 32: Who proved e is irrational?". How Euler did it. Mathematical Association of America. pp. 185–190. ISBN 978-0-88385-563-8. LCCN 2007927658.
  4. Cohn, Henry (2006). "A short proof of the simple continued fraction expansion of e". American Mathematical Monthly. Mathematical Association of America. 113 (1): 57–62. doi:10.2307/27641837. JSTOR 27641837.
  5. de Stainville, Janot (1815). Mélanges d'Analyse Algébrique et de Géométrie [A mixture of Algebraic Analysis and Geometry]. Veuve Courcier. pp. 340–341.
  6. MacDivitt, A. R. G.; Yanagisawa, Yukio (1987), "An elementary proof that e is irrational", The Mathematical Gazette, London: Mathematical Association, 71 (457): 217, doi:10.2307/3616765, JSTOR 3616765
  7. Penesi, L. L. (1953). "Elementary proof that e is irrational". American Mathematical Monthly. Mathematical Association of America. 60 (7): 474. JSTOR 2308411.
  8. Liouville, Joseph (1840). "Sur l'irrationalité du nombre e = 2,718". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 1 (in French). 5: 192.
  9. Liouville, Joseph (1840). "Addition à la note sur l'irrationnalité du nombre e". Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées. 1 (in French). 5: 193–194.
  10. Hurwitz, Adolf (1933) [1891]. "Über die Kettenbruchentwicklung der Zahl e". Mathematische Werke (in German). 2. Basel: Birkhäuser. pp. 129–133.
  11. Aigner, Martin; Ziegler, Günter M. (1998), Proofs from THE BOOK (4th ed.), Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag, pp. 27–36, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-00856-6, ISBN 978-3-642-00855-9.
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 11/1/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.